via
Western Spring
Western Spring Editor's Note: This is the transcript of a speech
made to a working class audience in 1884 by Karl Pearson, F.R.S.,
Professor of Applied Mathematics at University College, London.
Karl Pearson was a polymath, born
in Islington in 1857, he studied Mathematics at Cambridge University,
later Physics at the University of Heidelberg, and at various other
seats of learning; he studied metaphysics, physiology, Roman Law, 16th
Century German Literature, English Law and Socialism and became a
protégé of Sir Francis Galton.
Although influenced by
the socialism of Karl Marx, Pearson was a racialist, a eugenicist, a
socialist and a strong advocate of scientific nationalism and is
therefore arguably one of the founding fathers of National Socialism in
Britain.
*****
During
the past year there was a great deal of discussion in the newspapers —
and out of them –concerning the dwellings of the so-called poor.
Numerous philanthropical people wrote letters and articles describing
the extreme misery and unhealthy condition of many of our London courts
and alleys.
The Prince of Wales got up in the House
of Lords and remarked that he had visited several of the most deplorable
slums in the Holborn district, and found them “very deplorable indeed
!”
The whole subject seemed an excellent
one out of which to make political capital. The leader of the
Conservatives wrote an article in a Tory magazine on the dwellings of
the poor. He told us that things are much better in the country than
they are in the towns, that the great landlords look after the housing
of the agricultural labourers. It is the employers of labour, the
capitalists, who are at fault. THEY ought to provide proper dwellings
for their workpeople. This was the opinion of Lord Salisbury, a great
owner of land. But the Conservatives having come forward as the friends
of the working-men, it seemed impossible, with a view to future
elections, to let the matter rest there.
Accordingly, Mr. Joseph Chamberlain, a
Radical leader and capitalist, wrote another article in a Liberal
magazine, to show that it is no business whatever of the employers of
labour to look after the housing of their workpeople. It is the duty of
the owner of the land to see that decent houses are built upon it. In
other words, the only men, who under our present social regime could
make vast improvements, threw the responsibility off their own
shoulders.
“Very deplorable, indeed,” said Lord
Salisbury, ” but of course not the landlord’s fault ; why does not that
greedy fellow, the capitalist, look after his workpeople ?”
“ Nothing could be more wretched ; I am
sure it will lead to a revolution,” ejaculated Mr. Chamberlain,” but, of
course, it has nothing to do with the capitalist; why does not that
idle person, that absolutely useless landlord, build more decent
houses?”
Then the landlord and capitalist for
once agreed and thought it would be well to appoint a Royal Commission,
which meant, that after a certain amount of philanthropic twaddle and a
vast ocean of political froth the whole matter would end in nothing or
an absolutely fruitless Act of Parliament. Any change would have to be
made at the cost of either the landlord or capitalist, or of both, and
whether we like it or not, it is these two who practically govern this
country. They are not likely to empty their pockets for our benefit.
It is generally known how strong the
interest of the landlords is in both Houses of Parliament, but this is
comparatively small when we measure the interests of the capitalists.
You will be surprised, if you investigate the matter, to find the large
proportion of the House of Commons which represents the interests of
capital. The number of members of that House who are themselves
employers of labour, who are connected with great commercial interests,
who are chairmen or directors of large capitalistic companies, or in
some other way are representatives of capital (as well as of their
constituents) is quite astounding.
It is said that one large railway
company alone can muster forty votes on a division; while the railway
interests, if combined, might form a coalition which in conceivable
cases would be of extreme danger to the State. I have merely touched
upon this matter to remind you how thoroughly we are governed in this
country by a class. The government of this country is not in the hands
of the people. It is mere self-deception for us to suppose that all
classes have a voice in the management of our affairs.
The educative class (the class which
labours with its head) and the productive class (the class which labours
with its hands) have little or no real influence in the House of
Commons.
The governing class is the class of
wealth, in both of its branches — owners of land and owners of capital.
This class naturally governs in its own interests, and the interests of
wealth are what we must seek for would we understand the motive for any
particular form of foreign or domestic policy on the part of either
great State party.
It may strike you that I have wandered
very far from the topic with which I started, namely, the dwellings of
the poor, but I wanted to point out to you, by a practical example, how
very unlikely it is that a reform, urgently needed by one class of the
community, will be carried out efficiently by another governing class,
when that reform must be paid for out of the latter’s pockets.
Confirmation of this view may be drawn from the fact that the governing
class pretend to have discovered in 1884 only that the poor are badly
housed. There is something almost laughable in all the bother lately
raised about the housing of the poor.
So far as my own experience goes — and I
would ask if that is not a fact? — the poor are not worse housed — in
1884 — than they were in 1874. The evil is one of very old standing. It
was crying out for reform ten years ago, twenty years ago, forty years
ago. More than forty years ago in 1842 there was a report issued by a
“Commission on the sanitary condition of the labouring population of
Great Britain.” The descriptions given in that report are of a precisely
similar character to what was put before the public in a little tract
entitled the “Bitter Cry of Outcast London.” In that report we hear of
40,000 people in Liverpool alone living in cellars underground.
We are told that the annual number of
deaths from fever, generated by uncleanliness and overcrowding in the
dwellings of the poor, was then in England and Wales double the number
of persons killed in the battle of Waterloo. We hear of streets without
drainage, of workshops without ventilation, and of ten to twenty people
sleeping in the same room, often five in a bed, rarely with any regard
to sex. The whole essence of this report was to show that owing to the
great capitalistic industries, the working classes, if they had not
become poorer, had become more demoralized. They had been forced to
crowd together and occupy unhealthy and often ruinous dwellings.
The governing class and the public
authorities scarcely troubled themselves about the matter, but treated
the working classes as machines rather than as men. We see, then, that
precisely the same evil was crying loudly for remedy in 1842 as it cries
now in 1884. We ask why has there been no remedy applied during all
these years?
There can only be two answers to that
question ; either no remedy is possible, or else those in whose power
the remedy lies refuse to apply it. We must consider these two points.
Is no remedy possible?
Not long ago a thinking Conservative (if
such be not a contradiction in terms!) stated that although he
recognised the deplorable misery of the poorer members of the working
classes, he still held no remedy was possible. The misery might become
so intense that an outbreak would intervene; still, when the outbreak
was over, matters would sink back into their old course. There must be
poor, and the poor would be miserable. No violent revolution, no
peaceful reform, could permanently benefit the poorer class of toilers.
It was, so to speak, a law of nature (if not of God) that society should
have a basis of misery. History proved this to be always the case.
It is to this latter phrase I want to
call your attention — History proved this to be always the case. Our
Conservative friend was distinctly right in his method when he appealed
to history. That is peculiarly the method which ought to be made use of
for the solution of all social and political problems. It is of the
utmost importance to induce the working classes to study social and
political problems from the historical standpoint. Do not listen to mere
theory, or to the mere talk of rival political agitators. Endeavour, if
possible, to see how like problems have been treated by different
peoples in different ages, and with what measure of success.
The study of history is, I am aware,
extremely difficult, because the popular history books tell us only of
wars and of kings, and very little of the real life of the people — how
they worked, how they were fed, and how they were housed. But the real
mission of history is to tell us how the great mass of the people toiled
and lived; to tell us of their pleasure and of their misery. That is
the only history that can help us in social problems.
Does, then, history tell us that there
always has been, and therefore always must be, a large amount of misery
at the basis of society?
The question is one really of
statistics, and extremely difficult to answer; but after careful
investigation, I must state that I have come to a conclusion totally
different from that of our Conservative friend.
I admit, in the words of the man who
worked for the poor in Galilee, that at all times and places “the poor
are always with you”; but the amount of poverty as well as the degree of
misery attending it has varied immensely.
I have made special investigation of the
condition of the artisan class in Germany some three to four hundred
years ago, and do not hesitate to assert that anything like the
condition of the courts and dwellings of poorer London was then totally
unknown. If this be true, the argument from history is false. The
artisan class has occupied a firmer and more substantial position in
times gone by than it at present occupies.

If
it has sunk in the scale of comfort, it can certainly rise. In other
words, a remedy for the present state of things does seem to me
possible. Should any of you want to know why the working classes were
better off four hundred years ago than they are at present, I must state
it as my own opinion that it was due to a better social system. The
social system, so far as the workman was concerned, was based upon the
guild, and the political system of those old towns was based as a rule
upon the guilds. Thus the union which directed the workman in his work,
and brought his class together for social purposes, was practically the
same as that which directed the municipal government of his city.
If you would exactly understand what
that means, you must suppose the trades unions of to-day to take a large
share in the government of London. If they did so, how long do you
think the dwellings of the poor would remain what they are? Do you
believe the evil would remain another forty years or that in 1920 it
would be necessary to shuffle out of immediate action by another Royal
Commission?
As I have said, the guilds of working
men had originally a large share in municipal government. The city
guilds, as you know, are still very wealthy bodies, and have great
authority in the city. This is all that remains in London of the old
system of working men’s guilds taking a part in the management of the
city’s affairs. In old days, then, the labouring classes were united in
guilds and these guilds had a considerable share in local government.
The social and political system was thus, to some extent, based upon
labour. Such an organization of society, we call socialistic. The
workmen of four hundred years ago were better off than are the workmen
of today, because the old institutions were more socialistic — in other
words, society was organized rather on the basis of labour than the
basis of wealth.
A society based upon wealth, since it
grants power and place to the owners of something which is in the hands
of a few individuals, may be termed individualistic.
To-day we live in an individualistic
state. I believe the workman of four hundred years ago was better off
than his brother now, because he formed part of a socialistic rather
than an individualistic system. I believe a remedy possible for the
present state of affairs, because history seems to teach us that the
artisan has a firmer and happier position under a socialism than under
an individualism.
It also teaches us that some forms of
socialism have existed in the past, and may therefore be possible in the
present or future. I hold, and I would ask you to believe with me, that
a remedy is possible.
If it is, we are thrown back on the
alternative that the governing class has refused or neglected to apply
it. We have seen that the evil did not arise or did not accumulate to
such an extent where society was partly based upon labour; we are
therefore forced to the probable conclusion, that the evil has arisen
and continues to subsist, because our social and political system is
based upon wealth rather than upon labour — because we live under an
individualism rather than under a socialism.
It is the fault of our present social
system, and not a law of history, that the toilers should be condemned
to extreme misery and poverty. We have now to consider the following
questions:-
What do we mean by labour and a social system based upon labour?
By what means can we attempt to convert a
system based upon wealth to one based upon labour; in other words, how
shall we proceed to convert our present individualism into a socialism?
In the latter question it will be
necessary to include the consideration of the attitude which the artisan
class should itself take with regard to organizations for socialistic
change, and how it should endeavour to take political action especially
with regard to the two great capitalistic parties.
Let me first endeavour to explain what I
understand by labour. You may imagine, perhaps at first that I refer
only to labour of the hand — such labour as is required to make a pair
of boots or turn a lathe. But I conceive labour to be something of far
wider extent than this. I conceive it to include all work, whether work
of the head or of the hand, which is needful or profitable to the
community at large. The man who puts cargo into a ship is no more or
less a labourer than the captain who directs her course across the
ocean; nor is either more of a labourer than the mathematician or
astronomer whose calculations and observations enable the captain to
know which direction he shall take when he is many hundred miles from
land.
The shoemaker or the postman are no more
labourers than the clerk who sits in a merchant’s office or the judge
who sits on the bench. The schoolmaster, the writer and the actor are
all true labourers.
In some cases they may be overpaid; in
many they are underpaid. Men of wealth have been known to pay the
governess who teaches their children less than they pay their cook, and
treat her with infinitely less respect.
I have laid stress on the importance of
labour of the head, because I have met working men — although few — who
believed nothing but labour of the hand could have any value; all but
labourers with the hand were idlers. You have doubtless heard of the
victory gained last year by English troops in Egypt. Now, how do you
suppose that victory was gained?
Were the English soldiers a bit braver
than the Arabs? Were they stronger? Not in the least. They won the
victory because they were better disciplined, because they had better
weapons — shortly, because what we may term their organisation was
better. That organization was due to labour of the head.
Now, what happened in Egypt is going on
in the world at large every day. It is not always the stronger, but the
better organized, the better educated man who goes ahead. What is true
of individual men is true of nations. The better organised, the better
educated nation is victorious in the battle of life. We-English have
been so successful because we were well organized, because we were
better educated than Hindoos, Zulus, and all the races we have
conquered. You must never forget how much of that organization, that
education, is due to labourers with the head.
Some of you may be indifferent to the
great empire of England, to this superiority of Englishmen, but let me
assure you that, small as in some cases is the comfort of the English
working classes, it is on the average large compared with that of an
inferior race — compared, say, with the abject misery of the Egyptian
peasant.
I want, it possible, to point out to you
the need for sympathy between labour of all kinds — that labourers with
the hand and labourers with the head are mutually dependent. They are
both true labourers as opposed to the idlers — the drones, who, by some
chance having a monopoly of wealth, live on the labour of others.
I would say to every man — “Friend, what
is your calling, what are you doing for society at large, are you
making its shoes, are you teaching its children, are you helping to
maintain order and forward its business?”
If you are doing none of this, are you relieving its work hours by administering to its play?
Do you bring pleasure to the people as an actor, a writer, or a painter?
If you are doing none of this, if you
are simply a possessor of wealth, struggling to amuse yourself and pass
through life for your own pleasure, then — why, then, you are not wanted
here, and the sooner you clear out, bag and baggage, the better for us —
and perhaps for yourself.”
Do you grasp now the significance of a society based upon labour?
The possessor of wealth, simply because
he has wealth, would have no place in such a society. The workers would
remove him even as the worker bees eject the drones from their hive.
Society ought to be one vast guild of
labourers — workers with the head and workers with the hand — and so
organised there would be no place in it for those who merely live on the
work of others.
In a political or social system based
upon labour it would be the mere possessor of wealth who would have no
power; how far we are at present from such a socialism may be best
observed by noting that wealth now has almost all political and social
power, labour little or none.
We have now reached what I conceive to
be the fundamental axiom of Socialism. Society must be organised on the
basis of labour, and therefore, political power, the power of
organising, must be in the hands of labour.
That labour, as I have endeavoured to
impress upon you, is of two kinds. There is labour of the hand, which
provides necessaries for all society: there is the labour of the head,
which produces all that we term progress, and enables any individual
society to maintain its place in the battle of life — the labour which
educates and organises.
I have come across a tendency in some
workers with the hand to suppose all folk beside themselves to be idlers
— social drones, supported by their work. I admit that the great mass
of idlers are in what are termed the ‘upper and middle classes of
society’, but this arises from the fact that society, being graduated
solely according to wealth, the people with the most money, and who are
most idle, of course take their place in these viciously named ‘ upper
classes.’
In a labour scale they would naturally appear at the very bottom, and form ‘the dregs of population.’
It is true the labourer with the head
is, as a rule, better clothed, housed, and fed than the labourer with
the hand, but this often arises from the fact that he is also a
capitalist. Still, if the labourer with the head, whose labour is his
sole source of livelihood, is better clothed, housed, and fed than the
artisan, it does not show that in all cases he is earning more than his
due; on the contrary, it may denote that the artisan is earning far less
than his due. The difference, in fact, often represents the work which
goes to support the drones of our present social system.
At this point I reach what I conceive to
be the second great axiom of true Socialism. All forms of labour are
equally honourable. No form of labour which is necessary for society can
disgrace the man who practises it or place him in a lower social grade
than any other form of labour. Let us look at this point somewhat more
closely, for it is of the first importance.
So long as the worker looks upon his
work as merely work for himself — considers it only as a means to his
own subsistence, and values it only as it satisfies his own wants, so
long one form of work will be more degrading than another. To shovel mud
into a cart will be a lower form of work than to make a pair of shoes,
and to make shoes will not be such high-class labour as to direct a
factory. But there is another way of regarding work, in which all forms
of real labour appear of equal value — viz., when the labourer looks at
his work not with regard to himself, but with regard to society at
large.
Let him consider his work as something
necessary for society, as a condition of its existence, and then all
gradations vanish. It is just as necessary for society that its mud
should be cleared from the streets, as that it should have shoes, or
again, as that its factories should be directed.
Once let the workman recognise that his
labour is needful for society, and whatever its character, it becomes
honourable at once. In other words, from the social standpoint all
labour is equally honourable. We might even go so far as to assert that
the lowest forms of labour are the more honourable, because they involve
the greater personal sacrifice for the need of society.
Once let this second axiom of. true
Socialism be recognised — the equality of every form of labour –and all
the vicious distinctions of caste the false lines which society has
drawn between one class of workers and another must disappear. The
degradation of labour must cease.
Once admit that labour, though differing
in kind as the shoemaker’s from the blacksmith’s, is equal in degree,
and all class barriers are broken down. In other words, in a socialistic
state, or in a society based upon labour, there can be no difference of
class. All labourers, whether of the hand or the head, must meet on
equal terms; they are alike needful to society; their value will depend
only on the fashion and the energy with which they perform their
particular duties.

Before
leaving this subject of labour, there is one point, however, which must
be noticed. I have said that all forms of labour are equally
honourable, because we may regard them as equally necessary for society.
But still the effects of various kinds of labour on the individual will
be different. The man who spends his whole day in shovelling up mud
will hardly be as intelligent as the shoemaker or engineer. His labour
does not call for the same exercise of intelligence, nor draw out his
ingenuity to the same extent. Thus, although his labour is equally
honourable, it has not such a good influence on the man himself. Hence
the hours of labour, in such occupations, ought to be as short as
possible; sufficient leisure ought to be given to those engaged in the
more mechanical and disagreeable forms of toil to elevate and improve
themselves apart from their work.
When we admit that all labour is equally
honourable, and therefore deserving ot equal wage, then to educate the
labourer will not lead him to despise his work. It will only lead him to
appreciate and enjoy more fully his leisure.
This question of leisure is a matter of
the utmost importance. We hear much of the demand for shorter hours of
labour; but how is the increased spare time to be employed?
Many a toiler looks with envy upon the
extravagant luxury of the wealthy and cries, not unnaturally, “What
right have you to enjoy all this, while I can hardly procure the
necessaries of life?” But there is a matter in which I could wish the
working classes would envy the wealthy even more than they might
reasonably do their physical luxury — namely, their education: There is
to me something unanswerable in the cry which the workman might raise
against the wealthy — “What right have you to be educated, while I am
ignorant?” Far more unanswerable than the cry — “What right have you to
be rich while I am poor?”
I could wish a cry for education might
arise from the toilers as the cry for bread went up in the forties. It
is the one thing which would render an increase of leisure really
valuable to the workers — which would enable them to guide themselves,
and assist society through the dangerous storms which seem surely
gathering in the near future. Leisure employed in education, in
self-improvement, seems to me the only means by which the difference in
character between various forms of labour can be equalised. This appears
a point on which the labourers with the head can practically assist
those with the hand. Let the two again unite for that mutual assistance
which is so necessary, if between them they are to reorganise society
into one vast guild of labour.
If we pass for a moment from the
possibilities of the present to those of a distant future, we might
conceive the labourers with the hand to attain such a degree of
education that workers of both kinds might be fused together. The same
man might labour with his pen in the morning and with his shovel after
mid-day. That, I think, would be the ideal existence in which society,
as an entire body, would progress at the greatest possible rate. I have
endeavoured then, to lay before you what I understand by labour; how all
true labour is equally honourable and deserving of an equal wage. If
many of the anomalies, much of the misery of our present state of
society would disappear, were it organized on a socialistic or labour
basis, it then becomes necessary to consider in what manner the labour
basis differs from, and is opposed to, the present basis of wealth.
In order to illustrate what the present
basis of wealth means, let me put to you a hypothetical case. Let us
suppose three men on an island separated from the rest of the world. We
may also suppose there to be a sufficient supply of seed and ploughs,
and generally of agricultural necessaries. If now, one of the three men
were to assert that the island, the seed, and the ploughs belonged to
him, and his two comrades for some reason — or want of reason — accepted
his assertion, let us trace what would follow.
Obviously, he would have an entire
monopoly of all the means of sustaining life on the island. He could
part with them at whatever rate he pleased, and could insist upon the
produce of all the labour, which it would be possible to extract from
the two men, in return for supplying them with the barest necessities of
existence.
He would naturally do nothing; they
would till the ground with his implements, and sow his seed and store it
in his barn. After this he might employ them in work tending to
increase his luxuries, in providing him with as fine a house and as
gorgeous furniture as they were capable of producing.
He would probably allow them to build
themselves shanties as protection from the weather, and grant them
sufficient food to sustain life. All their time, after providing these
necessaries for themselves, would be devoted to his service. He would be
landlord and capitalist, having a complete monopoly of wealth. He could
practically treat the other two men as slaves.
Let us somewhat extend our example, and
suppose this relation to hold between the one man and a considerable
number of men on the island. Then it might be really advantageous for
all the people on the island if the one man directed their labour. We
may suppose him to be a practical farmer, who thoroughly understood his
business, so, by his directing the others, the greatest amount possible
would be produced from the land. As such a director of farming
operations, he would be a labourer with the head, and worthy as any man
under him to receive his hire. He would have as great a claim as any one
he directed to the necessaries of life produced by the labourers with
the hand. In a socialistic scheme he would still remain director; he
would still receive his share of the produce, and the result of the
labour of the community would be divided according to the labour of its
members.

On
the other hand, if our farm-director were owner of all things on the
island, he might demand not only the share due to him for his labour of
the head, but also that all the labour of the other inhabitants should
be directed to improving his condition rather than their own. After
providing for themselves the bare necessities of life, the other
islanders might be called upon to spend all the rest of their time in
ministering to his luxury. He could demand this because he would have a
monopoly of all the land and all the wealth of the island; such a state
of affairs on the island would be an individualism or a society based
upon wealth. I think this example will show clearly the difference
between a society based upon labour and one based upon wealth.
Commonplace as the illustration may
seem, it is one which can be extended, and yet rarely is extended to the
state of affairs we find in our own country. We have but to replace our
island-landowner and capitalist by a number of landowners and
capitalists. These will have a monopoly of land and of wealth. They can
virtually force the labouring classes, who have neither land nor
capital, to administer to their luxury in return for the more needful
supports of life. The limit of comfort to which they can reduce the
labouring classes depends on the following considerations, which, of
course, vary from time to time:-
First their own self-interest in keeping
at least a sufficient supply of labour in such decent health and
strength that it can satisfy their wants;
Secondly, their fear that too great pinching may lead to a forcible revolution; and
Thirdly, a sort of feeling arising
partly perhaps from religion, partly perhaps from purely mechanical
sympathy of dislike at the sight of suffering.
The greater demand there is for luxury
on the part of the wealthy, the smaller is the time that the labouring
classes can devote to the improvement of their own condition, the
increase of their own comfort.
Let us take a possible case, which may
not be the absolute truth, but which will exemplify the law we have
stated. Suppose that the labouring classes work eight hours a day. Now,
these eight hours are not only spent in producing the absolute
necessities of existence, and the degree of comfort in which our toilers
live, but in producing also all the luxuries enjoyed by the rich.
Let us suppose, for example, that five
hours suffice to sow and to till, and to weave and to carry and fetch —
shortly, to produce the food-supply of the country, and the average
comfort which the labourer enjoys as to house and raiment. What, then,
becomes of the other three hours’ work?
It is consumed in making luxuries of all
kinds for the wealthy, fine houses, rich furniture, dainty food, and so
forth. These three hours are spent, not in improving the condition of
the labourer’s own class, not in building themselves better dwellings or
weaving themselves better clothes, nor, on the other hand, are they
spent in public works for the benefit of the whole community but solely
in supplying luxuries for wealthy individuals. The wealthy can demand
these luxuries because they possess a monopoly of land and of capital,
shortly, of the means of subsistence. This monopoly of the means of
subsistence makes them in fact, if not in name, slave-owners.
Such is the result of the
individualistic as opposed to the socialistic system. We see now why the
houses of the poor are deplorable — namely, because that labour which
should be devoted to improving them is consumed in supplying the
luxuries of the rich. We may state it then, as a general law of a
society based upon wealth — that the misery of the labouring classes is
directly proportional to the luxury of the wealthy.
This law is a very old one indeed; the
only strange thing is, that it is every day forgotten. Having noted,
then, wherein the evil of the social system based upon wealth lies, we
have lastly to consider how far, and by what means, it is possible to
remedy it.
The only true method of investigating a
question of this kind is, I feel sure, the historical one. Let us ask
ourselves how in past ages one state of society has been replaced by
another, and then, if possible, apply the general law to the present
time.
Now, there are a considerable number of
socialistic teachers — I will not call them false Socialists — who are
never weary of crying out that our present state in society is extremely
unjust, and that it must be destroyed. They are perpetually telling the
labouring classes that the rich unjustly tyrannize over them, and that
this tyranny must be thrown off. According to these teachers, it would
seem as if the rich had absolutely entered into a conspiracy to defraud
the poor.
Now, although I call myself a Socialist,
I must tell you plainly that I consider such teaching not only very
foolish, but extremely harmful. It can arise only from men who are
ignorant, or from men who seek to win popularity from the
working-classes by appealing to their baser passions. So far from aiding
true Socialism, it stirs up class hatred, and instead of bringing
classes together, it raises a barrier of bitterness and hostility
between them.
It is idle to talk of a conspiracy of
the rich against the poor, of one class against another. A man is born
into his class, and into the traditions of his class. He is not
responsible for his birth, whether it be to wealth or to labour. He is
born to certain luxuries, and he is never taught to consider them as
other than his natural due; he does as his class does, and as his
fathers have done before him. His fault is not one of malice, but of
ignorance.
He does not know how his luxuries
directly increase the misery of the poor, because no one has ever
brought it home to him. Although a slave-owner he is an unconscious
slave-owner. Shortly, he wants educating; not educating quite in the
same sense as the labouring classes want educating, he probably has
book-learning enough. He wants teaching that there is a higher social
morality than the morality of a society based upon wealth.
Namely, he must be taught that mere
ownership has no social value at all — that the sole thing of social
value is labour, labour of head or labour of hand: and that individual
ownership of wealth has arisen in the past out of a very crude and
insufficient method of representing such labour.
The education of the so-called upper or
wealth-owning classes is thus an imperative necessity. They must be
taught a new morality. Here, again, is a point on which we see the need
of a union between the educative and hand-working classes. The labourers
with the head must come to the assistance of the labourers with the
hand by educating the wealthy.
Do not think this is a visionary
project; two great Englishmen at least, John Ruskin and William Morris,
are labouring at this task; they are endeavouring to teach the
capitalistic classes that the morality of a society based upon wealth is
a mere immorality. But you will tell me that education is a very long
process, and that meantime the poor are suffering and must continue to
suffer. Are not the labouring classes unjustly treated, and have they
not a right to something better? Shortly, ought they not to enforce that
right?

Pardon
me, if I tell you plainly that I do not understand what such abstract
‘justice ‘or ‘right’ means. I understand that the comfort of the
labouring classes is far below what it would be if society were
constituted on the basis of labour. I believe that on such a basis there
would be less misery in the world, and therefore it is a result to be
aimed at. But because this is a result which all men should strive for,
it does not follow that we gain anything by calling it a ‘right.’ A
‘right’ suggests something which a man may take by force, if he cannot
obtain it otherwise. It suggests that the labouring classes should
revolt against the capitalistic classes and seize what is their ‘right.’
Let us consider for a moment what is the meaning of such a revolt? I shall again take history as our teacher.
History shows us that whenever the
misery of the labouring classes reaches a certain limit, they always do
break into open rebellion. It is the origin, more or less, of all
revolutions throughout the course of time. But history teaches us just
as surely that such revolutions are accompanied by intense misery both
for the labouring and wealthy classes.
If this infliction of misery had ever
resulted in the reconstruction of society we might even hope for good
from a revolution, but we invariably find that something like the old
system springs again out of the chaos, and the same old distinction of
classes, the same old degradation of labour is sure to reappear. That is
precisely the teaching of the Paris Commune or again of the Anabaptist
Kingdom of God in Münster. Apart from this the labourers with the hand
will never be permanently successful in a revolution, unless they have
the labourers with the head with them; they will want organization, they
will want discipline, and this must fail unless education stands by
them.
Now, the labourers with the head have
usually deserted the labourers with the hand when the latter rise in
revolt, because they are students of history and they know too well from
history that revolution has rarely permanently benefited the revolting
classes. You may accept it as a primary law of history, that no great
change ever occurs with a leap, no great social reconstruction, which
will permanently benefit any class of the community, is ever brought
about by a revolution. It is the result of a gradual growth, a
progressive change, what we term an evolution. This is as much a law of
history as of nature.
Try as you will, you cannot make a man
out of a child in a day, you must wait and let him grow, and gradually
educate him and replace his childish ideas by the thoughts of a man.
Precisely so you must treat society; you must gradually change it,
educate it, if you want a permanent improvement in its nature.
Feeling, as I do the extreme misery
which is brought about by the present state of society based upon
wealth, I should say to the working-classes, ‘Revolt,’ if history did
not teach me only too surely, that revolution would fail of its object.
All progress towards a better state of
things must be gradual. Progress proceeds by evolution, not by
revolution. For this reason I would warn you against socialistic
teachers who talk loudly of ‘right ‘ and ‘justice ‘ — who seek to stir
up class against class. Such teaching merely tends towards revolution;
and revolution is not justifiable, because it is never successful. It
never achieves its object. Such teachers are not true socialists,
because they have not studied history; because their teaching really
impedes our progress towards socialism.
We might even take an example from our
island with its landlord-capitalist tyrannizing over the other
inhabitants. We have supposed him to be a practical farmer capable of
directing the labours of the others.
Now, suppose the inhabitants were to rise in revolt and throw him into the sea, what would happen?
Why, the very next year they would not
know what to sow or how to sow it; their agricultural operations would
fail, and there would very soon be a famine on the island, which would
be far worse than the old tyranny.
Something very similar would occur in
this country if the labouring classes were to throw all our capitalists
into the sea. There would be no one capable of directing the factories
or the complex operations of trade and commerce; these would all
collapse, and there would very soon be a famine in this island also.
You must bring your capitalist to see
that he is only a labourer, a labourer with the head, and deserves wage
accordingly. You can only do this by two methods. The first is to
educate him to a higher morality, the second is to restrict him by the
law of the land.
Now, the law of the land is nothing more
or less than the morality of the ruling class, and so long as political
power is in the hands of the capitalists, and these are ‘uneducated,’
they are unlikely to restrict their own profits. If, then, my view that
we can only approach socialism by a gradual change is correct, we have
before us two obvious lines of conduct which we may pursue at the same
time.
The first, and I am inclined to think
the more important, is the education of the wealthy classes; they must
be taught from childhood up that the only moral form of society is a
society based upon labour. They must be taught always to bear in mind
the great law — that the misery of the poor is ever directly
proportional to the luxury of the rich.
This first object ought to be
essentially the duty of the labourers with the head. Let the labourer
with the hand ever regard himself as working in concert with the
labourer with the head — the two are in truth but members of one large
guild, the guild of labour, upon which basis society has to be
reconstructed.
The second line of conduct, which is
practically open to all true Socialists, is the attainment of political
power; wealth must cease to be the governing power in this country, it
must be replaced by labour.
The educative classes and the
hand-workers must rule the country; only so will it be possible to
replace the wealth basis by the labour basis.
The first step in this direction must
necessarily be the granting of the franchise [the right to vote] to all
hand-workers. This is a very practical and definite aim to work for.
Now, I have already hinted that I
consider both great political parties really to represent wealth. Hence I
do not believe that any true Socialist is either Liberal or
Conservative, but at present it would be idle to think of returning
socialistic members to Parliament. Socialists will best forward their
aims at present by supporting that party which is likely to increase the
franchise. So that to be a true Socialist at present means, I think, to
support the ‘Liberal’ Government. This support is not given because we
are Liberals, but because by it, we can best aid the cause of Socialism.
But with regard to the franchise, there is a point which I cannot too
strongly insist upon. If the complete enfranchisement of the hand-worker
is to forward the socialistic cause he must be educated so as to use it
for that purpose.
Now, we have laid it down as a canon of
Socialism that all labour is equally honourable; in a society based upon
labour there can be no distinction of class. Thus, the true Socialist
must be superior to class-interests. He must look beyond his own class
to the wants and habits of society at large.
Hence, if the franchise is to be really
profitable, the hand-worker must be educated to see beyond the narrow
bounds of his own class. He must be taught to look upon society as a
whole, and respect the labour of all its varied branches. He must
endeavour to grasp the wants and habits of other forms of labour than
his own, whether it be labour of the head or of the hand.
He must recognize to the full that all
labour is equally honourable, and has equal claims on society at large.
The shoemaker does not despise the labour of the blacksmith, but he must
be quite sure that the labour of the schoolmaster, of the astronomer,
and of the man who works with his brains, is equally valuable to the
community.
Here again, we see how the labourer with the head can come to the assistance of the labourer with the hand.
In order that the franchise may be
practically of value to the artisan, he must grasp how to use it for
broader purposes than mere class aims. To do this he requires to educate
himself. I repeat that I should like to hear a cry go up from the
hand-workers for education and leisure for education, even as it went up
forty years ago for bread. For the mind is of equal importance with the
stomach and needs its bread also.

Apart
from the franchise, there is another direction in which, I think,
practical steps might be taken, namely, to obtain for trades-unions, or
rather, as I should prefer to call them, labour-guilds — a share or
influence in municipal government. Let there be a labour-guild influence
in every parish, and on every vestry. As I have said before, I cannot
conceive that the housing of the poor would be what it is if the trades
unions had been represented in the government of London.
Such a representation would be the first
approach to a communal organization based upon labour, and ultimately
to a society on the same basis. You can hardly support your
trades-unions too energetically, and you have in this respect taught the
labourers with the head a lesson.
These labourers with the head are just
beginning to form their labour-guilds too — guilds of teachers and
guilds of writers — and it is to these labour guilds, and to your
trades-unions that we must look for much useful work in the future.
These surely are practical aims enough
for the present, but I may perhaps be allowed to point out to you what
direction I think legislative action should take, supposing the
franchise granted to all hand-workers.
As I have endeavoured to show, any
sudden change would be extremely dangerous; it would upset our old
social arrangements, and would not give us any stable new institutions.
It would embitter class against class, and not destroy class altogether.
We must endeavour to pass gradually from the old to the new state; from
the state in which wealth is the social basis to one in which labour is
the sole element by which we judge men.
Now, in order that wealth should cease
to be mistress, her monopoly of the means of subsistence must be
destroyed. In other words, land and capital must cease to be in the
hands of individuals. We must have nationalization of the land and
nationalization of capital.
Every Socialist is a land-nationalizer
and a capital-nationalizer. It will be sufficient now to consider the
first problem, the nationalization of the land.
Mr. George says, take the land and give
no compensation. That [is what I term a revolutionary measure; it
attempts to destroy and reconstruct in a moment.
If history teaches us anything, it tells
us that all such revolutionary measures fail; they bring more misery
than they accomplish good. Hence, although I am a land-nationalizer — as
every Socialist must be — I do not believe in Mr. George’s cry of ‘No
compensation.’
Then we have another set of land-nationalizers who would buy the landlords out. Let us see what this means.
The landlords would be given, ‘in
return’ for their lands, a large sum of money, which would have to be
borrowed by the nation, and the interests on which would increase for
ever the taxes of the country. In other words, we should be perpetuating
the wealth of the landlords and their claims to be permanently
supported by the classes that labour. That is not a socialistic remedy.
It would seem, at first sight as if
there were no alternative — either compensation or no compensation. Yet I
think there is a third course, if we would only try to legislate for
the future as well as for the present.
Suppose a bill were passed to convert
all freehold in land into a leasehold, say, of 80 to 100 years, from the
nation. Here there would be no question of compensation, and little
real injury to the present landowner, because the difference between
freehold and a hundred years’ leasehold (at least in towns) is
comparatively small. At the end of a hundred years the nation would be
in possession of all land without having paid a penny for it, and
without violently breaking up the present social arrangements. In less
than 100 years with the land slipping from their fingers the children of
our present landowners would have learnt that, if they want to live,
they must labour. That would be a great step to true socialism.
Precisely as I propose to treat the land
I would treat most forms of capital. With the land, of course, mines
and factories would necessarily pass into the hands of the nation.
Railways would have to be dealt with in the same fashion. The present
companies would have a hundred years’ lease instead of a perpetuity of
their property.
These are merely suggestions of how it
might be possible to pass to a stable form of society based upon labour
to a true socialism. The change would be stable because it would be
gradual; the state would be socialistic because it would be based upon
labour; while wealth, in its two important forms land and capital would
belong alone to the nation.
Some oi you may cry out in astonishment,
“But what is the use of working for such a socialism, we shall never
live to see it, we shall never enjoy its happiness.”
Quite true, I reply, but there is a
nobler calling than working for ourselves, there is a higher happiness
than self-enjoyment, namely, the feeling that our labour will have
rendered posterity, will have rendered our children free from the misery
through which we ourselves have had to struggle; the feeling that our
work in life has left the world a more joyous dwelling-place for mankind
than we found it. The little streak of improvement which each man may
leave behind him — the only immortality of which mankind can be sure —
is a far nobler result of labour, whether of hand or of head, than
three-score years of unlimited personal happiness.